A Theory of Justice
by
John Rawls

Copyright 1971 Harvard University Press

CHAPTER 1: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS

3. THE MAIN IDEA OF THE THEORY OF JUSTICE
My aim is to present a conception of justice which generalizes and carries to a higher level of abstraction the familiar theory of the social contract as found, say, in Locke, Rousseau, and Kant.4  In order to do this we are not to think of the original contract as one to enter a particular society or to set up a particular form of government. Rather, the guiding idea is that the principles of justice for the basic structure of society are the object of the original agreement. They are the principles that free and rational persons concerned to further their own interests would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the fundamental terms of their association. These principles are to regulate all further agreements; they specify the kinds of social cooperation that can be entered into and the forms of government that can be established. This way of regarding the
principles of justice I shall call justice as fairness.


Thus we are to imagine that those who engage in social cooperation choose together, in one joint act, the principles which are to assign basic rights and duties and to determine the division of social benefits. Men are to decide in advance how they are to regulate their claims against one another and what is to be the foundation charter of their society. Just as each person must decide by rational reflection what constitutes his good, that is, the system of ends which

4. As the text suggests, I shall regard Locke's Second Treatise of Government, Rousseau's The Social Contract, and Kant's ethical works beginning with The Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals as definitive of the contract tradition. F.or all of its greatness, Hobbes's Leviathan raises special problems. A general hIstorical survey is provided by J. W. Gough, The Social Contract, 2nd ed. (Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1957), and Otto Gierke, Natural Law and the Theory of Society, trans. with an introduction by Ernest Barker (Cambridge, The University Press, 1934). A presentation of the contract view as primarily an ethical theory is to be found in G. R. Grice, The Grounds of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, The University Press, 1967). See also §19, note 30.

 

p.12

it is rational for him to pursue, so a group of persons must decide once and for all what is to count among them as just and unjust. The choice which rational men would make in this hypothetical situation of equal liberty, assuming for the present that this choice problem has a solution, determines the principles of justice.


In justice as fairness the original position of equality corresponds to the state of nature in the traditional theory of the social contract. This original position is not, of course, thought of as an actual historical state of affairs, much less as a primitive condition of culture. It is understood as a purely hypothetical situation characterized so as to lead to a certain conception of justice.5 Among the essential features of this situation is that no one knows his place in society, his class position or social status, nor does anyone know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence, strength, and the like. I shall even assume that the parties do not know their conceptions of the good or their special psychological propensities. The principles of justice are chosen behind a veil of ignorance. This ensures that no one is advantaged or disadvantaged in the choice of principles by the outcome of natural chance or the contingency of social circumstances. Since all are similarly situated and no one is able to design principles to favor his particular condition, the principles of justice are the result of a fair agreement or bargain. For given the circumstances of the original position, the symmetry of everyone's relations to each other, this initial situation is fair between individuals as moral persons, that is, as rational beings with their own ends and capable, I shall assume, of a sense of justice. The original position is, one might say, the appropriate initial status quo, and thus the fundamental agreements reached in it are fair. This explains the propriety of the name "justice as fairness": it conveys the idea that the principles of justice are agreed to in an initial situation that is fair. The name does not mean that the con-

5. Kant is clear that the original agreement is hypothetical. See The Metaphysics of Morals, pt. I (Rechtslehre), especially §§47, 52; and pt. II of the essay "Concerning the Common Saying: This May Be True in Theory but It Does Not Apply in Practice," in Kant's Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss and trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge, The University Press, 1970), pp. 73-87. See Georges Vlachos, La Pensee politique de Kant (Paris, Presses Universitaires de France, 1962), pp. 326-335; and J. G. Murphy, Kant: The Philosophy of Right (London, Macmillan, 1970), pp. 109-112, 133-136, for a further discussion.


p.13

cepts of justice and fairness are the same, any more than the phrase "poetry as metaphor" means that the concepts of poetry and metaphor are the same.


Justice as fairness begins, as I have said, with one of the most general of all choices which persons might make together, namely, with the choice of the first principles of a conception of justice which is to regulate all subsequent criticism and reform of institutions. Then, having chosen a conception of justice, we can suppose that they are to choose a constitution and a legislature to enact laws, and so on, all in accordance with the principles of justice initially agreed upon. Our social situation is just if it is such that by this sequence of hypothetical agreements we would have contracted into the general system of rules which defines it.  Moreover, assuming that the original position does determine a set of principles (that is, that a particular conception of justice would be chosen), it will then be true that whenever social institutions satisfy these principles those engaged in them can say to one another that they are cooperating on terms to which they would agree if they were free and equal persons whose relations with respect to one another were fair. They could all view their arrangements as meeting the stipulations which they would acknowledge in an initial situation that embodies widely accepted and reasonable constraints on the choice of principles.  The general recognition of this fact would provide the basis for a public acceptance of the corresponding principles of justice. No society can, of course, be a scheme of cooperation which men enter voluntarily in a literal sense; each person finds himself placed at birth in some particular position in some particular society, and the nature of this position materially affects his life prospects.  Yet a society satisfying the principles of justice as fairness comes as close as a society can to being a voluntary scheme, for it meets the principles which free and equal persons would assent to under circumstances that are fair. In this sense its members are autonomous and the obligations they recognize self-imposed.


One feature of justice as fairness is to think of the parties in the initial situation as rational and mutually disinterested. This does not mean that the parties are egoists, that is, individuals with only certain kinds of interests, say in wealth, prestige, and domination.  But they are conceived as not taking an interest in one another's interests.

p.14

They are to presume that even their spiritual aims may be opposed, in the way that the aims of those of different religions may be opposed. Moreover, the concept of rationality must be interpreted as far as possible in the narrow sense, standard in economic theory, of taking the most effective means to given ends.  I shall modify this concept to some extent, as explained later (§ 25), but one must try to avoid introducing into it any controversial ethical elements.  The initial situation must be characterized by stipulations that are widely accepted.

In working out the conception of justice as fairness one main task clearly is to determine which principles of justice would be chosen in the original position.  To do this we must describe this situation in some detail and formulate with care the problem of choice which it presents.  These matters I shall take up in the immediately succeeding chapters. It may be observed, however, that once the principles of justice are thought of as arising from an original agreement in a situation of equality, it is an open question whether the principle of utility would be acknowledged.  Offhand it hardly seems likely that persons who view themselves as equals, entitled to press their claims upon one another, would agree to a principle which may require lesser life prospects for some simply for the sake of a greater sum of advantages enjoyed by others.  Since each desires to protect his interests, his capacity to advance his conception of the good, no one has a reason to acquiesce in an enduring loss for himself in order to bring about a greater net balance of satisfaction.  In the absence of strong and lasting benevolent impulses, a rational man would not accept a basic structure merely because it maximized the algebraic sum of advantages irrespective of its permanent effects on his own basic rights and interests.  Thus it seems that the principle of utility is incompatible with the conception of social cooperation among equals for mutual advantage.  It appears to be inconsistent with the idea of reciprocity implicit in the notion of a well-ordered society.  Or, at any rate, so I shall argue.

I shall maintain instead that the persons in the initial situation would choose two rather different principles: the first requires equality in the assignment of basic rights and duties, while the second holds that social and economic inequalities, for example inequalities of wealth and authority, are just only if they result in compensating

p.15

benefits for everyone, and in particular for the least advantaged members of society. These principles rule out justifying institutions on the grounds that the hardships of some are offset by a greater good in the aggregate.  It may be expedient but it is not just that some should have less in order that others may prosper. But there is no injustice in the greater benefits earned by a few provided that the situation of persons not so fortunate is thereby improved.  The intuitive idea is that since everyone's well-being depends upon a scheme of cooperation without which no one could have a satisfactory life, the division of advantages should be such as to draw forth the willing cooperation of everyone taking part in it, including those less well situated. Y et this can be expected only if reasonable terms are proposed.  The two principles mentioned seem to be a fair agreement on the basis of which those better endowed, or more fortunate in their social position, neither of which we can be said to deserve, could expect the willing cooperation of others when some workable scheme is a necessary condition of the welfare of all.6  Once we decide to look for a conception of justice that nullifies the accidents of natural endowment and the contingencies of social circumstance as counters in quest for political and economic advantage, we are led to these principles. They express the result of leaving aside those aspects of the social world that seem arbitrary from a moral point of view.

The problem of the choice of principles, however, is extremely difficult.  I do not expect the answer I shall suggest to be convincing to everyone.  It is, therefore, worth noting from the outset that justice as fairness, like other contract views, consists of two parts: (1) an interpretation of the initial situation and of the problem of choice posed there, and (2) a set of principles which, it is argued, would be agreed to.  One may accept the first part of the theory (or some variant thereof), but not the other, and conversely.  The concept of the initial contractual situation may seem reasonable although the particular principles proposed are rejected. To be sure, I want to maintain that the most appropriate conception of this situation does lead to principles of justice contrary to utilitarianism and perfectionism, and therefore that the contract doctrine provides an alternative to these views.  Still, one may dispute this contention even though

6. For the formulation of this intuitive idea I am indebted to Allan Gibbard.

p.16

one grants that the contractarian method is a useful way of studying ethical theories and of setting forth their underlying assumptions.

Justice as fairness is an example of what I have called a contract theory.  Now there may be an objection to the term "contract" and related expressions, but I think it will serve reasonably well.  Many words have misleading connotations which at first are likely to confuse.  The terms "utility" and "utilitarianism" are surely no exception. They too have unfortunate suggestions which hostile critics have been willing to exploit; yet they are clear enough for those prepared to study utilitarian doctrine.  The same should be true of the term "contract" applied to moral theories.  As I have mentioned, to understand it one has to keep in mind that it implies a certain level of abstraction.  In particular, the content of the relevant agreement is not to enter a given society or to adopt a given form of government, but to accept certain moral principles.  Moreover, the undertakings referred to are purely hypothetical: a contract view holds that certain principles would be accepted in a well-defined initial situation.

The merit of the contract terminology is that it conveys the idea that principles of justice may be conceived as principles that would be chosen by rational persons, and that in this way conceptions of justice may be explained and justified.  The theory of justice is a part, perhaps the most significant part, of the theory of rational choice.  Furthermore, principles of justice deal with conflicting claims upon the advantages won by social cooperation; they apply to the relations among several persons or groups.  The word "contract" suggests this plurality as well as the condition that the appropriate division of advantages must be in accordance with principles acceptable to all parties.  The condition of publicity for principles of justice is also connoted by the contract phraseology.  Thus, if these principles are the outcome of an agreement, citizens have a knowledge of the principles that others follow.  It is characteristic of contract theories to stress the public nature of political principles.  Finally there is the long tradition of the contract doctrine.  Expressing the tie with this line of thought helps to define ideas and accords with natural piety.  There are then several advantages in the use of the term "contract."  With due precautions taken, it should not be misleading.

p.17

A final remark. Justice as fairness is not a complete contract theory. For it is clear that the contractarian idea can be extended to the choice of more or less an entire ethical system, that is, to a system including principles for all the virtues and not only for justice.  Now for the most part I shall consider only principles of justice and others closely related to them; I make no attempt to discuss the virtues in a systematic way.  Obviously if justice as fairness succeeds reasonably well, a next step would be to study the more general view suggested by the name "rightness as fairness."  But even this wider theory fails to embrace all moral relationships, since it would seem to include only our relations with other persons and to leave out of account how we are to conduct ourselves toward animals and the rest of nature.  I do not contend that the contract notion offers a way to approach these questions which are certainly of the first importance; and I shall have to put them aside.  We must recognize the limited scope of justice as fairness and of the general type of view that it exemplifies.  How far its conclusions must be revised once these other matters are understood cannot be decided in advance.

4. THE ORIGINAL POSITION AND JUSTIFICATION
I have said that the original position is the appropriate initial status quo which insures that the fundamental agreements reached in it are fair.  This fact yields the name '.justice as fairness."  It is clear, then, that I want to say that one conception of justice is more reasonable than another, or justifiable with respect to it, if rational persons in the initial situation would choose its principles over those of the other for the role of justice.  Conceptions of justice are to be ranked by their acceptability to persons so circumstanced.  Understood in this way the question of justification is settled by working out a problem of deliberation: we have to ascertain which principles it would be rational to adopt given the contractual situation.  This connects the theory of justice with the theory of rational choice.

If this view of the problem of justification is to succeed, we must, of course, describe in some detail the nature of this choice problem.  A problem of rational decision has a definite answer only if we know

p.18

the beliefs and interests of the parties, their relations with respect to one another, the alternatives between which they are to choose, the procedure whereby they make up their minds, and so on.  As the circumstances are presented in different ways, correspondingly different principles are accepted.  The concept of the original position, as I shall refer to it, is that of the most philosophically favored interpretation of this initial choice situation for the purposes of a theory of justice.

But how are we to decide what is the most favored interpretation?  I assume, for one thing, that there is a broad measure of agreement that principles of justice should be chosen under certain conditions.   To justify a particular description of the initial situation one shows that it incorporates these commonly shared presumptions. One argues from widely accepted but weak premises to more specific conclusions.  Each of the presumptions should by itself be natural and plausible; some of them may seem innocuous or even trivial.  The aim of the contract approach is to establish that taken together they impose significant bounds on acceptable principles of justice.  The ideal outcome would be that these conditions determine a unique set of principles; but I shall be satisfied if they suffice to rank the main traditional conceptions of social justice.

One should not be misled, then, by the somewhat unusual conditions which characterize the original position.  The idea here is simply to make vivid to ourselves the restrictions that it seems reasonable to impose on arguments for principles of justice, and therefore on these principles themselves.  Thus it seems reasonable and generally acceptable that no one should be advantaged or disadvantaged by natural fortune or social circumstances in the choice of principles.  It also seems widely agreed that it should be impossible to tailor principles to the circumstances of one's own case.  We should insure further that particular inclinations and aspirations, and persons' conceptions of their good do not affect the principles adopted. The aim is to rule out those principles that it would be rational to propose for acceptance, however little the chance of success, only if one knew certain things that are irrelevant from the standpoint of justice.  For example, if a man knew that he was wealthy, he might find it rational to advance the principle that various taxes for wel-

p.19

fare measures be counted unjust; if he knew that he was poor, he would most likely propose the contrary principle.  To represent the desired restrictions one imagines a situation in which everyone is deprived of this sort of information.  One excludes the knowledge of those contingencies which sets men at odds and allows them to be guided by their prejudices.  In this manner the veil of ignorance is arrived at in a natural way.  This concept should cause no difficulty if we keep in mind the constraints on arguments that it is meant to express.  At any time we can enter the original position, so to speak, simply by following a certain procedure, namely, by arguing for principles of justice in accordance with these restrictions.

It seems reasonable to suppose that the parties in the original position are equal.  That is, all have the same rights in the procedure for choosing principles; each can make proposals, submit reasons for their acceptance, and so on.  Obviously the purpose of these conditions is to represent equality between human beings as moral persons, as creatures having a conception of their good and capable of a sense of justice.  The basis of equality is taken to be similarity in these two respects.  Systems of ends are not ranked in value; and each man is presumed to have the requisite ability to understand and to act upon whatever principles are adopted.  Together with the veil of ignorance, these conditions define the principles of justice as those which rational persons concerned to advance their interests would consent to as equals when none are known to be advantaged or disadvantaged by social and natural contingencies.

There is, however, another side to justifying a particular description of the original position.  This is to see if the principles which would be chosen would match our considered convictions of justice or extend them in an acceptable way: We can note whether applying these principles would lead us to make the same judgments about the basic structure of society which we now make intuitively and in which we have the greatest confidence; or whether, in cases where our present judgments are in doubt and given with hesitation, these principles offer a resolution which we can affirm on reflection.  There are questions which we feel sure must be answered in a certain way.  For example, we are confident that religious intolerance and racial discrimination are unjust.  We think that we have examined these

p.20

things with care and have reached what we believe is an impartial judgment not likely to be distorted by an excessive attention to our own interests.  These convictions are provisional fixed points which we presume any conception of justice must fit.  But we have much less assurance as to what is the correct distribution of wealth and authority.  Here we may be looking for a way to remove our doubts.  We can check an interpretation of the initial situation, then, by the capacity of its principles to accommodate our firmest convictions and to provide guidance where guidance is needed.

In searching for the most favored description of this situation we work from both ends.  We begin by describing it so that it represents generally shared and preferably weak conditions.  We then see if these conditions are strong enough to yield a significant set of principles.  If not, we look for further premises equally reasonable. But if so, and these principles match our considered convictions of justice, then so far well and good. But presumably there will be discrepancies. In this case we have a choice.  We can either modify the account of the initial situation or we can revise our existing judgments, for even the judgments we take provisionally as fixed points are liable to revision.  By going back and forth, sometimes altering the conditions of the contractual circumstances, at others withdrawing our judgments and conforming them to principle, I assume that eventually we shall find a description of the initial situation that both expresses reasonable conditions and yields principles which match our considered judgments duly pruned and adjusted.  This state of affairs I refer to as reflective equilibrium.  It is an equilibrium because at last our principles and judgments coincide; and it is reflective since we know to what principles our judgments conform and the premises of their derivation.  At the moment everything is in order.  But this equilibrium is not necessarily stable.  It is liable to be upset by further examination of the conditions which should be imposed on the contractual situation and by particular

7. The process of mutual adjustment of principles and considered judgments Is not peculiar to moral philosophy. See Nelson Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Fore- cast (Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1955), pp. 65-68, for parallel remarks concerning the justification of the principles of deductive and inductive inference.


p.21

cases which may lead us to revise our judgments. Yet for the time being we have done what we can to render coherent and to justify our convictions of social justice. We have reached a conception of the original position.

I shall not, of course, actually work through this process.  Still, we may think of the interpretation of the original position that I shall present as the result of such a hypothetical course of reflection.   It represents the attempt to accommodate within one scheme both reasonable philosophical conditions on principles as well as our considered judgments of justice.  In arriving at the favored interpretation of the initial situation there is no point at which an appeal is made to self-evidence in the traditional sense either of general conceptions or particular convictions.  I do not claim for the principles of justice proposed that they are necessary truths or derivable from such truths.   A conception of justice cannot be deduced from self-evident premises or conditions on principles; instead, its justification is a matter of the mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view.

A final comment. We shall want to say that certain principles of justice are justified because they would be agreed to in an initial situation of equality.  I have emphasized that this original position is purely hypothetical.  It is natural to ask why, if this agreement is never actually entered into, we should take any interest in these principles, moral or otherwise.  The answer is that the conditions embodied in the description of the original position are ones that we do in fact accept.  Or if we do not, then perhaps we can be persuaded to do so by philosophical reflection.  Each aspect of the contractual situation can be given supporting grounds.  Thus what we shall do is to collect together into one conception a number of conditions on principles that we are ready upon due consideration to recognize as reasonable.  These constraints express what we are prepared to regard as limits on fair terms of social cooperation.  One way to look at the idea of the original position, therefore, is to see it as an expository device which sums up the meaning of these conditions and helps us to extract their consequences.  On the other hand, this conception is also an intuitive notion that suggests its own elaboration, so that led on by it we are drawn to define more clearly the standpoint

p.22

from which we can best interpret moral relationships.  We need a conception that enables us to envision our objective from afar: the intuitive notion of the original position is to do this for us.8

p.54

CHAPTER 2: THE PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE

The theory of justice may be divided into two main parts: (1) an interpretation of the initial situation and a formulation of the various principles available for choice there, and (2) an argument establishing which of these principles would in fact be adopted. In this chapter two principles of justice for institutions and several principles for individuals are discussed and their meaning explained. Thus I am concerned for the present with only one aspect of the first part of the theory.  Not until the next chapter do I take up the interpretation of the initial situation and begin the argument to show that the principles considered here would indeed be acknowledged.  A variety of topics are discussed: institutions as subjects of justice and the concept of formal justice; three kinds of procedural justice; the place of the theory of the good; and the sense in which the principles of justice are egalitarian, among others.  In each case the aim is to explain the meaning and application of the principles.

 

p.60

11. TWO PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE

I shall now state in a provisional form the two principles of justice that I believe would be agreed to in the original position. The first formulation of these principles is tentative.  As we go on I shall consider several formulations and approximate step by step the final statement to be given much later.  I believe that doing this allows the exposition to proceed in a natural way.  

The first statement of the two principles reads as follows:

First: each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive scheme of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for others.

Second: social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone's advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all.

p.61

There are two ambiguous phrases in the second principle, namely "everyone's advantage" and "open to all."  Determining their sense more exactly will lead to a second formulation of the principle in  §13. The final version of the two principles is given in § 46; §39 considers the rendering of the first principle.

By way of general comment, these principles primarily apply, I have said, to the basic structure of society.  They are to govern the assignment of rights and duties and to regulate the distribution of social and economic advantages.  As their formulation suggests, these principles presuppose that the social structure can be divided into two more or less distinct parts, the first principle applying to the one, the second to the other. They distinguish between those aspects of the social system that define and secure the equal liberties of citizenship and those that specify and establish social and economic inequalities. The basic liberties of citizens are, roughly speaking, political liberty (the right to vote and to be eligible for public office) together with freedom of speech and assembly; liberty of conscience and freedom of thought; freedom of the person along with the right to hold (personal) property; and freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure as defined by the concept of the rule of law.  These liberties are all required to be equal by the first principle, since citizens of a just society are to have the same basic rights.

The second principle applies, in the first approximation, to the distribution of income and wealth and to the design of organizations that make use of differences in authority and responsibility.  While the distribution of wealth and income need not be equal, it must be to everyone's advantage, and at the same time, positions of authority and responsibility must be accessible to all.  One applies the second principle by holding positions open, and then, subject to this constraint, arranges social and economic inequalities so that everyone benefits.

These principles are to be arranged in a serial order with the first principle prior to the second.  This ordering means that infringements of the basic equal liberties protected by the first principle cannot be justified, or compensated for, by greater social and economic advantages. These liberties have a central range of application within which they can be limited and compromised only when they conflict with other basic liberties.  Since they may be limited when they clash with one another, none of these liberties is absolute; but however they are adjusted to form one system, this system is to be the same for all.  It is difficult, and perhaps impossible, to give a complete specification of these liberties independently from the particular circumstances--social, economic, and technological--of a given society.  The hypothesis is that the general form of such a list could be devised with sufficient exactness to sustain this conception of justice.  Of course, liberties not on the list, for example, the right to own certain kinds of property (e.g., means of production) and freedom of contract as understood by the doctrine of laissez-faire are not basic; and so they are not protected by the priority of the first principle.  Finally, in regard to the second principle, the distribution of wealth and income, and positions of authority and responsibility, are to be consistent with both the basic liberties and equality of opportunity.

p.62

It is clear that these two principles are rather specific in their content, and their acceptance rests on certain assumptions that I must eventually try to explain and justify.  A theory of justice depends upon a theory of society in ways that will become evident as we proceed.  For the present, it should be observed that the two principles (and this holds for all formulations) are a special case of a more general conception of justice that can be expressed as follows.

AIl social values-liberty and opportunity, income and wealth, and the bases of self-respect-are to be distributed equally unless an unequal distribution of any, or all, of these values is to everyone's advantage.

Injustice, then, is simply inequalities that are not to the benefit of all.  Of course, this conception is extremely vague and requires interpretation.

As a first step, suppose that the basic structure of society distributes certain primary goods, that is, things that every rational man is presumed to want.  These goods normally have a use whatever a person's rational plan of life.  For simplicity, assume that the chief primary goods at the disposition of society are rights and liberties, powers and opportunities, income and wealth. (Later on in Part Three the primary good of self-respect has a central place.)  These are the social primary goods.  Other primary goods such as health and vigor, intelligence and imagination, are natural goods; although their possession is influenced by the basic structure, they are not so directly under its control.  Imagine, then, a hypothetical initial arrangement in which all the social primary goods are equally distributed: everyone has similar rights and duties, and income and wealth are evenly shared.  This state of affairs provides a benchmark for judging improvements.  If certain inequalities of wealth and organizational powers would make everyone better off than in this hypothetical starting situation, then they accord with the general conception.

Now it is possible, at least theoretically, that by giving up some of their fundamental liberties men are sufficiently compensated by the resulting social and economic gains.  The general conception of justice imposes no restrictions on what sort of inequalities are permissible; it only requires that everyone's position be improved.  We need not suppose anything so drastic as consenting to a condition of

p.63

slavery. Imagine instead that men forego certain political rights when the economic returns are significant and their capacity to influence the course of policy by the exercise of these rights would be marginal in any case.  It is this kind of exchange which the two principles as stated rule out; being arranged in serial order they do not permit) exchanges between basic liberties and economic and social gains.  The serial ordering of principles expresses an underlying preference among primary social goods. When this preference is rational so likewise is the choice of these principles in this order.

In developing justice as fairness I shall, for the most part, leave aside the general conception of justice and examine instead the special case of the two principles in serial order.  The advantage of this procedure is that from the first the matter of priorities is recognized and an effort made to find principles to deal with it.  One is led to attend throughout to the conditions under which the acknowledgment of the absolute weight of liberty with respect to social and economic advantages, as defined by the lexical order of the two principles, would be reasonable.  Offhand, this ranking appears extreme and too special a case to be of much interest; but there is more justification for it than would appear at first sight.  Or at any rate, so I shall maintain (§ 82). Furthermore, the distinction between fundamental rights and liberties and economic and social benefits marks a difference among primary social goods that one should try to exploit.  It suggests an important division in the social system.  Of course, the distinctions drawn and the ordering proposed are bound to be at best only approximations.  There are surely circumstances in which they fail.  But it is essential to depict clearly the main lines of a reasonable conception of justice; and under many conditions anyway, the two principles in serial order may serve ,well enough.  When necessary we can fall back on the more general conception.

The fact that the two principles apply to institutions has certain consequences.  Several points illustrate this.  First of all, the rights and liberties referred to by these principles are those which are defined by the public rules of the basic structure. Whether men are free is determined by the rights and duties established by the major institutions of society.  Liberty is a certain pattern of social forms.  The first principle simply requires that certain sorts of rules, those

p.64

defining basic liberties, apply to everyone equally and that they allow the most extensive liberty compatible with a like liberty for all.  The only reason for circumscribing the rights defining liberty and making men's freedom less extensive than it might otherwise be is that these equal rights as institutionally defined would interfere with one another.

Another thing to bear in mind is that when principles mention persons, or require that everyone gain from an inequality, the reference is to representative persons holding the various social positions, or offices, or whatever, established by the basic structure.  Thus in applying the second principle I assume that it is possible to assign an expectation of well-being to representative individuals holding these positions.  This expectation indicates their life prospects as viewed from their social station.  In general, the expectations of representative persons depend upon the distribution of rights and duties throughout the basic structure. When this changes, expecta­tions change. I assume, then, that expectations are connected: by raising the prospects of the representative man in one position we presumably increase or decrease the prospects of representative men in other positions.  Since it applies to institutional forms, the second principle (or rather the first part of it) refers to the expectations of representative individuals.  As I shall discuss below, neither principle applies to distributions of particular goods to particular individuals who may be identified by their proper names.  The situation where someone is considering how to allocate certain commodities to needy persons who are known to him is not within the scope of the principles.  They are meant to regulate basic institutional arrangements.  We must not assume that there is much similarity from the standpoint of justice between an administrative allotment of goods to specific persons and the appropriate design of society.  Our common sense intuitions for the former may be a poor guide to the latter.

Now the second principle insists that each person benefit from permissible inequalities in the basic structure.  This means that it must be reasonable for each relevant representative man defined by this structure, when he views it as a going concern, to prefer his prospects with the inequality to his prospects without it.  One is not allowed to justify differences in income or organizational powers on the ground that the disadvantages of those in one position are out-

p. 65

weighed by the greater advantages of those in another.  Much less can infringements of liberty be counterbalanced in this way.  Applied to the basic structure, the principle of utility would have us maximize the sum of expectations of representative men (weighted by the number of persons they represent, on the classical view); and this would permit us to compensate for the losses of some by the gains of others.  Instead, the two principles require that everyone benefit from economic and social inequalities.  It is obvious, however, that there are indefinitely many ways in which all may be advantaged when the initial arrangement of equality is taken as a benchmark.  

p.75

13. DEMOCRATIC EQUALITY AND THE DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE

The democratic interpretation, as the table suggests, [deleted] is arrived at by combining the principle of fair equality of opportunity with the difference principle .... [This allows one to choose a single efficient position from which to judge social and economic inequalities] Assuming the framework of institutions required by equal liberty and fair equality of opportunity, the higher expectations of those better situated are just if and only if they work as part of a scheme which improves the expectations of the least advantaged members of society. The intuitive idea is that the social order is not to establish and secure the more attractive prospects of those better off unless doing so is to the advantage of those less fortunate ....

p.77

To illustrate the difference principle, consider the distribution of income among social classes.  Let us suppose that the various income groups correlate with representative individuals by reference to whose expectations we can judge the distribution.  Now those starting out as members of the entrepreneurial class in property-owning democracy, say, have a better prospect than those who begin in the class of unskilled laborers.  It seems likely that this will be true even when the social injustices which now exist are removed.  What, then, can possibly justify this kind of initial inequality in life prospects?  According to the difference principle, it is justifiable only if the difference in expectation is to the advantage of the representative man who is worse off, in this case the representative unskilled worker.  The inequality in expectation is permissible only if lowering it would make the working class even more worse off.  Supposedly, given the rider in the second principle concerning open positions, and the principle of liberty generally, the greater expectations allowed to entrepreneurs encourages them to do things which raise the prospects of laboring class.  Their better prospects act as incentives so that the economic process is more efficient, innovation proceeds at a faster pace, and so on.   Eventually the resulting material benefits spread throughout the system and to the least advantaged.  I shall not consider how far these things are true.  The point is that something of this kind must be argued if these inequalities are to satisfy by the difference principle.  ....

p.100

17. THE TENDENCY TO EQUALITY

I wish to conclude this discussion of the two principles by explaining the sense in which they express an egalitarian conception of justice. Also I should like to forestall the objection to the principle of fair opportunity that it leads to a meritocratic society.  In order to prepare the way for doing this, I note several aspects of the conception of justice that I have set out.

First we may observe that the difference principle gives some weight to the considerations singled out by the principle of redress.  This is the principle that undeserved inequalities call for redress; and since inequalities of birth and natural endowment are undeserved, these inequalities are to be somehow compensated for.18 Thus the principle holds that in order to treat all persons equally, to provide genuine equality of opportunity, society must give more attention to those with fewer native assets and to those born into the less favorable social positions.  The idea is to redress the bias

p.101

of contingencies in the direction of equality.   In pursuit of this principle greater resources might be spent on the education of the less rather than the more intelligent, at least over a certain time of life, say the earlier years of school.

Now the principle of redress has not to my knowledge been proposed as the sale criterion of justice, as the single aim of the social order.  It is plausible as most such principles are only as a prima facie principle, one that is to be weighed in the balance with others.  For example, we are to weigh it against the principle to improve the average standard of life, or to advance the common good.19 But whatever other principles we hold, the claims of redress are to be taken into account.  It is thought to represent one of the elements in our conception of justice.  Now the difference principle is not of course the principle of redress.  It does not require society to try to even out handicaps as if all were expected to compete on a fair basis in the same race.  But the difference principle would allocate resources in education, say, so as to improve the long-term expectation of the least favored.  If this end is attained by giving more attention to the better endowed, it is permissible; otherwise not.  And in making this decision, the value of education should not be assessed solely in terms of economic efficiency and social welfare.  Equally if not more important is the role of education in enabling a person to enjoy the culture of his society and to take part in its affairs, and in this way to provide for each individual a secure sense of his own worth.

Thus although the difference principle is not the same as that of redress, it does achieve some of the intent of the latter principle.  It transforms the aims of the basic structure so that the total scheme of institutions no longer emphasizes social efficiency and technocratic values.  The difference principle represents, in effect, an agreement to regard the distribution of natural talents as in some respects a common asset and to share in the greater social and economic benefits made possible by the complementarities of this distribution.  Those who have been favored by nature, whoever they are, may gain from their good fortune only on terms that improve the situation of those who have lost out.  The naturally advantaged are not to gain merely because they are more gifted, but only to

p.102

cover the costs of training and education and for using their endowments in ways that help the less fortunate as well.  No one deserves his greater natural capacity nor merits a more favorable starting place in society.  But, of course, this is no reason to ignore, much less to eliminate these distinctions. Instead, the basic structure can be arranged so that these contingencies work for the good of the least fortunate.  Thus we are led to the difference principle if we wish to set up the social system so that no one gains or loses from his arbitrary place in the distribution of natural assets or his initial position in society without giving or receiving compensating advantages in return.

In view of these remarks we may reject the contention that the ordering of institutions is always defective because the distribution of natural talents and the contingencies of social circumstance are unjust, and this injustice must inevitably carryover to human arrangements. Occasionally this reflection is offered as an excuse for ignoring injustice, as if the refusal to acquiesce in injustice is on a par with being unable to accept death.  The natural distribution is neither just nor unjust; nor is it unjust that persons are born into society at some particular position.  These are simply natural facts.  What is just and unjust is the way that institutions deal with these facts.  Aristocratic and caste societies are unjust because they make these contingencies the ascriptive basis for belonging to more or less enclosed and privileged social classes.  The basic structure of these societies incorporates the arbitrariness found in nature.  But there is no necessity for men to resign themselves to these contingencies. The social system is not an unchangeable order beyond human control but a pattern of human action. Injustice as fairness men agree to avail themselves of the accidents of nature and social circumstance only when doing so is for the common benefit.  The two principles are a fair way of meeting the arbitrariness of fortune; and while no doubt imperfect in other ways, the institutions which satisfy these principles are just. ...

p.118

...

20. THE NATURE OF THE ARGUMENT FOR CONCEPTIONS OF JUSTICE

The intuitive idea of justice as fairness is to think of the first principles of justice as themselves the object of an original agreement in a suitably defined initial situation.  These principles are those which rational persons concerned to advance their interests would accept in this position of equality to settle the basic terms of their

p.119

association. It must be shown, then, that the two principles of justice I are the solution for the problem of choice presented by the original position.  In order to do this, one must establish that, given the circumstances of the parties, and their knowledge, beliefs, and interests, an agreement on these principles is the best way for each person to secure his ends in view of the alternatives available.

Now obviously no one can obtain everything he wants; the mere existence of other persons prevents this.  The absolutely best for any man is that everyone else should join with him in furthering his conception of the good whatever it turns out to be.  Or failing this, that all others are required to act justly but that he is authorized to exempt himself as he pleases. Since other persons will never agree to such terms of association these forms of egoism would be rejected. The two principles of justice, however, seem to be a reasonable proposal. In fact, I should like to show that these principles are everyone's best reply, so to speak, to the corresponding demands of the others.  In this sense, the choice of this conception of justice is the unique solution to the problem set by the original position.

By arguing in this way one follows a procedure familiar in social theory.  That is, a simplified situation is described in which rational individuals with certain ends and related to each other in certain ways are to choose among various courses of action in view of their knowledge of the circumstances.  What these individuals will do is then derived by strictly deductive reasoning from these assumptions about their beliefs and interests, their situation and the options open to them.  Their conduct is, in the phrase of Pareto, the resultant of tastes and obstacles.1  In the theory of price, for example, the equilibrium of competitive markets is thought of as arising when many individuals each advancing his own interests give way to each other what they can best part with in return for what they most desire.  Equilibrium is the result of agreements freely struck between willing traders.  For each person it is the best situation that he can reach by free exchange consistent with the right and freedom of others to further their interests in the same way.  It is for this reason that this state of affairs is an equilibrium, one that will persist in the absence of further changes in the circumstances.  No

1. Manuel d'économie politique ( Paris , 1909), ch. III, §23. Pareto says: "L'equilbre résulte précisément de cette opposition des goûts et des obstacles."

 

p.136

24. THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE

The idea of the original position is to set up a fair procedure so that any principles agreed to will be just.  The aim is to use the notion of pure procedural justice as a basis of theory.  Somehow we must nullify the effects of specific contingencies which put men at odds and tempt them to exploit social and natural circumstances to their own advantage. Now in order to do this I assume that the parties are situated behind a veil of ignorance.  They do not know how the various alternatives will affect their own particular case

p.137

and they are obliged to evaluate principles solely on the basis of general considerations.11

It is assumed, then, that the parties do not know certain kinds of particular facts.  First of all, no one knows his place in society, his class position or social status; nor does he know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence and strength, and the like.  Nor, again, does anyone know his conception of the good, the particulars of his rational plan of life, or even the special features of his psychology such as his aversion to risk or liability to optimism or pessimism.  More than this, I assume that the parties do not know the particular circumstances of their own society.  That is, they do not know its economic or political situation, or the level of civilization and culture it has been able to achieve.  The persons in the original position have no information as to which generation they belong.  These broader restrictions on knowledge are appropriate in part because questions of social justice arise between generations as well as within them, for example, the question of the appropriate rate of capital saving and of the conservation of natural resources and the environment of nature.  There is also, theoretically anyway, the question of a reasonable genetic policy.  In these cases too, in order to carry through the idea of the original position, the parties must not know the contingencies that set them in opposition. They must choose principles the consequences of which they are prepared to live with whatever generation they turn out to belong to.

As far as possible, then, the only particular facts which the parties know is that their society is subject to the circumstances of justice and whatever this implies.  It is taken for granted, however, that they know the general facts about human society.  They understand political affairs and the principles of economic theory; they know the basis of social organization and the laws of human psychology.  Indeed, the parties are presumed to know whatever general facts affect the choice of the principles of justice. There are

11. The veil of ignorance is so natural a condition that something like it must have occurred to many.  The closest explicit statement of it known to me is found in J. C. Harsanyi, "Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking," Journal of Political Economy, vol. 61 (1953). Harsanyi uses it to develop a utilitarian theory, as I discuss below in §§27-28.

 

p. 138

no limitations on general information, that is, on general laws and theories, since conceptions of justice must be adjusted to the characteristics of the systems of social cooperation which they are to regulate, and there is no reason to rule out these facts.  It is, for example, a consideration against a conception of justice that, in view of the laws of moral psychology, men would not acquire a desire to act upon it even when the institutions of their society satisfied it. For in this case there would be difficulty in securing the stability of social cooperation.  It is an important feature of a conception of justice that it should generate its own support.  That is, its principles should be such that when they are embodied in the basic structure of society men tend to acquire the corresponding sense of justice. Given the principles of moral learning, men develop a desire to act in accordance with its principles.  In this case a conception of justice is stable. This kind of general information is admissible in the original position.

...

p.139

These remarks show that the original position is not to be thought of as a general assembly which includes at one moment everyone who will live at some time; or, much less, as an assembly of everyone who could live at some time.  It is not a gathering of all actual or possible persons.  To conceive of the original position in either of these ways is to stretch fantasy too far; the conception would cease to be a natural guide to intuition.  In any case, it is important that the original position be interpreted so that one can at any time adopt its perspective.  It must make no difference when one takes up this viewpoint, or who does so: the restrictions must be such that the same principles are always chosen.  The veil of ignorance is a key condition in meeting this requirement.  It insures not only that that information available is relevant, but that it is at all times the same.

It may be protested that the condition of the veil of ignorance is irrational. Surely, some may object, principles should be chosen in the light of all the knowledge available.  There are various replies to this contention.  Here I shall sketch those which emphasize the simplifications that need to be made if one is to have any theory at all. ... To begin with, it is clear that since the differences among the parties are unknown to them, and everyone is equally rational and similarly situated, each is convinced by the same arguments.  Therefore, we can view the choice in the original position from the standpoint of one person selected at random.  If anyone after due reflection prefers a conception of justice to another, then they all do, and a unanimous agreement can be reached.  ...

Thus there follows the very important consequence that the parties have no basis for bargaining in the usual sense.  No one knows his situation in society nor his natural assets, and therefore no one is in a position to tailor principles to his advantage. We

p.140

might imagine that one of the contractees threatens to hold out unless the others agree to principles favorable to him.  But how does he know which principles are especially in his interests?  The same holds for the formation of coalitions: if a group were to decide to band together to the disadvantage of the others, they would not know how to favor themselves in the choice of principles.  Even if they could get everyone to agree to their proposal, they would have no assurance that it was to their advantage, since they cannot identify themselves either by name or description.  ... 

p.142

...

25. THE RATIONALITY OF THE PARTIES

I have assumed throughout that the persons in the original position I are rational.  In choosing between principles each tries as best he can to advance his interests.  But I have also assumed that the parties do not know their conception of the good.  This means that while they know that they have some rational plan of life, they do not know the details of this plan, the particular ends and interests which it is calculated to promote.  How, then, can they decide which conceptions of justice are most to their advantage?  Or must we suppose that they are reduced to mere guessing?  To meet this difficulty, I postulate that they accept the account of the good touched upon in the preceding chapter: they assume that they would prefer more primary social goods rather than less.  Of course, it may turn out, once the veil of ignorance is removed, that some of them for religious or other reasons may not, in fact, want more of these goods.

p.143

But from the standpoint of the original position, it is rational for the parties to suppose that they do want a larger share, since in any case they are not compelled to accept more if they do not wish to, nor does a person suffer from a greater liberty.  Thus even though the parties are deprived of information about their particular ends, they have enough knowledge to rank the alternatives. They know that in general they must try to protect their liberties, widen their opportunities, and enlarge their means for promoting their aims whatever these are. Guided by the theory of the good and the general facts of moral psychology, their deliberations are no longer guesswork.  They can make a rational decision in the ordinary sense.

The concept of rationality invoked here, with the exception of one essential feature, is the standard one familiar in social theory.14 Thus in the usual way, a rational person is thought to have a coherent set of preferences between the options open to him.  He ranks these options according to how well they further his purposes; he follows the plan which will satisfy more of his desires rather than less, and which has the greater chance of being successfully executed. The special assumption I make is that a rational individual does not suffer from envy.  He is not ready to accept a loss for himself if only others have less as well.  He is not downcast by the knowledge or perception that others have a larger index of primary social goods. Or at least this is true as long as the differences between himself and others do not exceed certain limits, and he does not believe that the existing inequalities are founded on injustice or are the result of letting chance work itself out for compensating social purpose (§ 80).

14. For this notion of rationality, see the references to Sen and Arrow above, §23, note 9.  The discussion in I. M. D. Little, The Critique of Welfare Economics, 2nd ed. (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1957), ch. II, is also relevant here. For rational choice under uncertainty, see below §26, note 18. H. A. Simon discusses the limitations of the classical conceptions of rationality and the need for  a more realistic theory in "A Behavioral Model of Rational Choice," Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 69 (1955).  See also his essay in Surveys of Economic Theory, vol. 3 (London, Macmillan, 1967).  For philosophical discussions see Donald Davidson, "Actions, Reasons, and Causes," Journal of Philosophy, vol. 60 (1963); C. G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation (New York, The Free Press, 1965), pp. 463-486; Jonathan Bennett, Rationality (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1964), and J. D. Mabbott, "Reason and Desire," Philosophy, vol. 28 (1953).

p.251

40. THE KANTIAN INTERPRETATION OF JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS

For the most part I have considered the content of the principle of equal liberty and the meaning of the priority of the rights that it defines.  It seems appropriate at this point to note that there is a Kantian interpretation of the conception of justice from which this principle derives. This interpretation is based upon Kant's notion of autonomy.  It is a mistake, I believe, to emphasize the place of generality and universality in Kant's ethics.  That moral principles are general and universal is hardly new with him; and as we have seen these conditions do not in any case take us very far.  It is impossible to construct a moral theory on so slender a basis, and therefore to limit the discussion of Kant's doctrine to these notions is to reduce it to triviality.  The real force of his view lies elsewhere.29

For one thing, he begins with the idea that moral principles are the object of rational choice.  They define the moral law that men can rationally will to govern their conduct in an ethical commonwealth.  Moral philosophy becomes the study of the conception and outcome of a suitably defined rational decision. This idea has im-

29. To be avoided at all costs is the idea that Kant's doctrine simply provides the general, or formal, elements for a utilitarian (or indeed for any other) theory.  See, for example, R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason (Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1963), pp. 123f.  One must not lose sight of the full scope of his view, one must take the later works into consideration.  Unfortunately, there is no commentary on Kant's moral theory as a whole; perhaps it would prove impossible to write.  But the standard works of H. J. Paton, The Categorical Imperative (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1948), and L. W. Beck, A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1960), and others need to be further complemented by studies of the other writings.  See here M. J. Gregor's Laws of Freedom (Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1963), an account of The Metaphysics of Morals, and J. G. Murphy's brief Kant: The Philosophy of Right (London, Macmillan, 1970). Beyond this, The Critique of Judgment, Religion within the Limits of Reason, and the political writings cannot be neglected without distorting his doctrine.  For the last, see Kant's Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss and trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge, The University Press, 1970).

p.252

mediate consequences.  For once we think of moral principles as legislation for a kingdom of ends, it is clear that these principles must not only be acceptable to all but public as well.  Finally Kant supposes that this moral legislation is to be agreed to under conditions that characterize men as free and equal rational beings.  The description of the original position is an attempt to interpret this conception.  I do not wish to argue here for this interpretation on the basis of Kant's text.  Certainly some will want to read him differently.  Perhaps the remarks to follow are best taken as suggestions for relating justice as fairness to the high point of the contractarian tradition in Kant and Rousseau.

Kant held, I believe, that a person is acting autonomously when the principles of his action are chosen by him as the most adequate possible expression of his nature as a free and equal rational being. The principles he acts upon are not adopted because of his social position or natural endowments, or in view of the particular kind of society in which he lives or the specific things that he happens to want. To act on such principles is to act heteronomously. Now the veil of ignorance deprives the persons in the original position of the knowledge that would enable them to choose heteronomous principles. The parties arrive at their choice together as free and equal rational persons knowing only that those circumstances obtain which give rise to the need for principles of justice.

To be sure, the argument for these principles does add in various ways to Kant's conception. For example, it adds the feature that the principles chosen are to apply to the basic structure of society; and premises characterizing this structure are used in deriving the principles of justice. But I believe that this and other additions are natural enough and remain fairly close to Kant's doctrine, at least when all of his ethical writings are viewed together. Assuming, then, that the reasoning in favor of the principles of justice is correct, we can say that when persons act on these principles they are acting in accordance with principles that they would choose as rational and independent persons in an original position of equality. The principles of their actions do not depend upon social or natural contingencies, nor do they reflect the bias of the particulars of their plan of life or the aspirations that motivate them.  By acting from these principles persons express their nature as free and equal rational beings

p.253

subject to the general conditions of human life.  For to express one's nature as a being of a particular kind is to act on the principles that would be chosen if this nature were the decisive determining element. ...  

The principles of justice are also categorical imperatives in Kant's sense.  For by a categorical imperative Kant understands a principle of conduct that applies to a person in virtue of his nature as a free and equal rational being.  The validity of the principle does not presuppose that one has a particular desire or aim.  Whereas a hypothetical imperative by contrast does assume this: it directs us to take certain steps as effective means to achieve a specific end.  Whether the desire is for a particular thing, or whether it is for something more general, such as certain kinds of agreeable feelings or pleasures, the corresponding imperative is hypothetical.   Its applicability depends upon one's having an aim which one need not have as a condition of being a rational human individual.  The argument for the two principles of justice does not assume that the parties have particular ends, but only that they desire certain primary goods.  These are things that it is rational to want whatever else one wants.  Thus given human nature, wanting them is part of being rational; and while each is presumed to have some conception of the good, nothing is known about his final ends.  The preference for primary goods is derived, then, from only the most general assumptions about rationality and the conditions of human life.  To act from the principles of justice is to act from categorical imperatives in the sense that they apply to us whatever in particular our aims are.  This simply reflects the fact that no such contingencies appear as premises in their derivation.

We may note also that the motivational assumption of mutual disinterest accords with Kant's notion of autonomy, and gives another reason for this condition. So far this assumption has been used to characterize the circumstances of justice and to provide a clear conception to guide the reasoning of the parties.  We have also seen that the concept of benevolence, being a second-order notion, would not work out well. Now we can add that the assumption of mutual disinterest is to allow for freedom in the choice of a system of final ends.30 Liberty in adopting a conception of the good is limited only by principles that are deduced from a doctrine which imposes no prior constraints on these conceptions.  Presuming mutual disinterest in the original position carries out this idea.  We postulate that the parties have opposing claims in a suitably general sense.  If their ends were restricted in some specific way, this would appear at the outset as an arbitrary restriction on freedom.  Moreover, if the parties were conceived as altruists, or as pursuing certain kinds of pleasures, then the principles chosen would apply, as far as the argument would have shown, only to persons whose freedom was restricted to choices compatible with altruism or hedonism.  As the argument now runs, the principles of justice cover all persons with rational plans of life, whatever their content, and these principles represent the appropriate restrictions on freedom.  Thus it is possible to say that the constraints on conceptions of the good are the result of an interpretation of the contractual situation that puts no prior limitations on what men may desire.  There are a variety of reasons, then, for the motivational premise of mutual disinterest.  This premise is not only a matter of realism about the circumstances of justice or a way to make the theory manageable.  It also connects up with the Kantian idea of autonomy. ...

p.256

...

Properly understood, then, the desire to act justly derives in part from the desire to express most fully what we are or can be, namely free and equal rational beings with a liberty to choose.  It is for this reason, I believe, that Kant speaks of the failure to act on the moral law as giving rise to shame and not to feelings of guilt.  And this is appropriate, since for him acting unjustly is acting in a manner that fails to express our nature as a free and equal rational being.  Such actions therefore strike at our self-respect, our sense of our own worth, and the experience of this loss is shame (§ 67).  We have acted as though we belonged to a lower order, as though we were a creature whose first principles are decided by natural contingencies.  Those who think of Kant's moral doctrine as one of law and guilt badly misunderstand him. Kant's main aim is to deepen and to justify Rousseau's idea that liberty is acting in accordance with a law that we give to ourselves. And this leads not to a morality of austere command but to an ethic of mutual respect and self­esteem.32

The original position may be viewed, then, as a procedural interpretation of Kant's conception of autonomy and the categorical imperative. The principles regulative of the kingdom of ends are those that would be chosen in this position, and the description of this situation enables us to explain the sense in which acting from these principles expresses our nature as free and equal rational persons.  No longer are these notions purely transcendent and lacking explicable connections with human conduct, for the procedural conception of the original position allows us to make these ties.  ... 

32. See B. A. O. Williams, "The Idea of Equality," in Philosophy, Politics and Society, Second Series, ed. Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1962), pp. 115f. For confirmation of this interpretation, see Kant's remarks on moral education in The Critique of Practical Reason, pt. II. See also Beck, A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 233-236.

p. 302

Having noted these cases of priority, I now wish to give the final statement of the two principles of justice for institutions. For the sake of completeness, I shall give a full statement including earlier formulations.

First Principle
Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all.

Second Principle
Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both:

(a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle, and
(b) attached to offices and positions open to all under condi­tions of fair equality of opportunity.

First Priority Rule (The Priority of Liberty )
The principles of justice are to be ranked in lexical order and therefore liberty can be· restricted only for the sake of liberty. There are two cases:

(a) a less extensive liberty must strengthen the total system of liberty shared by all;
(b) a less than equal liberty must be acceptable to those with the lesser liberty.

Second Priority Rule (The Priority of Justice over Efficiency and Welfare)
The second principle of justice is lexically prior to the principle of efficiency and to that of maximizing the sum of advantages; and

p.303

fair opportunity is prior to the difference principle. There are two cases:

(a) an inequality of opportunity must enhance the opportunities of those with the lesser opportunity;
(b) an excessive rate of saving must on balance mitigate the burden of those bearing this hardship.

General Conception

All social primary goods--liberty and opportunity, income and wealth, and the bases of self-respect--are to be distributed equally unless an unequal distribution of any or all of these goods is to the advantage of the least favored.